Etica & Politica / Ethics & Politics, 2003, 1

http://www.units.it/~dipfilo/etica_e_politica/2003_1/16_monographica.htm

 

 

 

An Interview with John Randolph Lucas

by Barbara Giolito

 

Barbara Giolito:    What are the philosophical premises that played a significant role at the origin of your argument? In particular, what weight had the liar paradox?

 

John Randolph Lucas: I formulated an argument somewhat analogous to the Liar Paradox when I was arguing against another boy at school. He was putting forward an extreme form of materialism, and I argued that his action in arguing for it showed that he believed in the power of reason, and belied his contention that only material causes were effective.

 

B. G.: As it is not possible to recognize the truth of goedelian sentences because it is not possible to proof the consistency of a consistent system, is it correct - in your opinion - to maintain that we cannot say that the difference between human mind and computer is in our ability to "see" a truth that computers cannot see, but - at the most - that we can suppose this truth?

 

J. R. L.: But it is possible to recognise the truth of goedelian sentences. We can and do recognise it. All that Goedel's Second Theorem shows is that we cannot give a "formal" proof of it. I discuss at length reasons for holding our minds to be basically consistent.

So it isn't correct to maintain that we cannot say that the difference between human mind and computer is in our ability to "see" a truth that computers cannot see, but-at the most- that we can suppose this truth.

 

B. G.: Human consistence's hypothesis could be not a more likely hypothesis than the idea of using faculties as creativity and fantasy as points of difference between human beings and machines. What would you reply to such an argument? In your opinion, your argument has a different power in comparison with arguments using human properties as creativity and fantasy?

 

J. R. L.: I think that creativity etc. are important differences between human minds and machines. But this point is not conceded by hard-line mechanists. My argument is aimed at them. It does not adduce all the most important differences between human minds and machines, but concentrates on one incontrovertible one, which even a mechanist cannot push aside.

 

B. G.: If - for every machine M - a stronger machine can exist able to recognize the goedelian sentence of M, human mind could not be a machine able to recognize goedelian sentences of weaker machines but not its own goedelian sentence, provable by a stronger machine?

 

J. R. L.: A human mind can in principle recognise its own Goedelian sentence.

 

B. G.:  According to your opinion that your goedelian argument is not a direct proof that mind is not a machine but a dialectical argument, a schema of disproof for any particular version of mechanism, what do you think about attempts to use the Goedel's theorem as proof against Artificial Intelligence (for instance, that one made by professor Roger Penrose)?

 

J. R. L.: Penrose's argument is very similar to mine. In "Turn over the Page" I wrote "Roger Penrose uses not Goedel's theorem itself but one of its corollaries, Turing's theorem, which he applies to the whole world-wide activity of all mathematicians put together, and claims that their creative activity cannot be completely accounted for by any algorithm, any set of rigid rules that a Turing machine could be programmed to follow. I used Goedel's theorem itself, and considered only individuals, reasonably numerate (able to follow and understand Goedel's theorem) but not professional mathematicians. I did not give a direct argument, but rather a schema of disproof, whereby any claim that a particular individual could be adequately represented by a Turing machine could be refuted. My version was, designedly, much less formal than the others, partly because I was addressing a not-very-numerate audience, but chiefly because I was not giving a direct disproof, but rather a schema which needed to be adapted to refute the particular case being propounded by the other side".

 

 B. G.: What do you think about hopes, set by professor Roger Penrose and by Connectionists, on saving A.I. project by means of quantistic computers or connectionist ones? Is it possible to eliminate these questions saying that these kinds of computer have nothing to do with mechanism because they are dynamical systems? In any case, do you think that these projects can be useful, from a practical point of view, in studying human mind?

 

J. R. L.: They may be, in so far as they are not mechanist.

 

B. G.: What do you think about the idea that not the whole mind but the greater part of it is a machine?

 

J. R. L.: Some parts may be, but it is difficult to divide the mind into parts.

 

B. G.: According to the idea of Mechanists that only formal proofs are valid ones and according to your idea that your argument is not a proof but a schema of refutation, Mechanists could not reply to your argument maintaining that it is too idealised?

 

J. R. L.: It is not that idealised. If the mechanist puts forward a specific claim that a mind is a particular machine, I can show him to be wrong.

 

B. G.: Goedel himself maintained - during the 25th Josiah Willard Gibbs Conference (26th December 1951, Providence) - that the incompleteness theorem on his own, without other philosophical premises, could not lead to the impossibility of producing a machine able to proof mathematical theorems provable by human minds; what do you think about this subject?

 

J. R. L.: In Turn over the Page, again, I wrote "Goedel argues for a disjunction: an Either/Or, with the strong suggestion that the second disjunct is untenable, and hence by Modus Tollendo Ponens that the first disjunct must be true. "So the following disjunctive is inevitable: Either mathematics is incompletable in this sense, that its evident axioms can never be comprised in a finite rule, that is to say, the human mind (even within the realm of pure mathematics) infinitely surpasses the powers of any finite machine, or else there exist absolutely unsolvable diophantine problems of the type specified […]. It is clear that Goedel thought the second disjunct false, so that by Modus Tollendo Ponens he was implicitly denying that any Turing machine could emulate the powers of the human mind.